How Can Et Jaynes Probability Theory Help With Priors Selection?

2025-09-03 04:16:19 220

4 Answers

Grayson
Grayson
2025-09-05 17:31:05
I get a little giddy whenever Jaynes comes up because his way of thinking actually makes prior selection feel like crafting a story from what you truly know, not just picking a default. In my copy of 'Probability Theory: The Logic of Science' I underline whole paragraphs that insist priors should reflect symmetries, invariances, and the constraints of real knowledge. Practically that means I start by writing down the facts I have — what units are natural, what quantities are invariant if I relabel my data, and what measurable constraints (like a known average or range) exist.

From there I often use the maximum entropy principle to turn those constraints into a prior: if I only know a mean and a range, MaxEnt gives the least-committal distribution that honors them. If there's a natural symmetry — like a location parameter that shifts without changing the physics — I use uniform priors on that parameter; for scale parameters I look for priors invariant under scaling. I also do sensitivity checks: try a Jeffreys prior, a MaxEnt prior, and a weakly informative hierarchical prior, then compare posterior predictions. Jaynes’ framework is a mindset as much as a toolbox: encode knowledge transparently, respect invariance, and test how much your conclusions hinge on those modeling choices.
Zoe
Zoe
2025-09-06 04:22:46
I tend to tackle priors like I’d prep for a boss fight in a game: gather intel, exploit symmetry, and don’t overcommit to flashy choices. I’ll ask three quick questions: what do I truly know (constraints), what transformations should leave the problem unchanged, and how sensitive is my conclusion to the prior? Jaynes pushes using maximum entropy to encode exactly what you know and nothing more, so if I only know a mean and variance I pick the MaxEnt distribution for those constraints rather than guessing a shape.

A concrete habit I picked up is to try invariance arguments first: if the system is unchanged under shifts, consider a flat prior on location; if it’s unchanged by scale, consider a prior proportional to 1/parameter. But I never stop there — I run posterior predictive checks and priors sensitivity runs. If the posterior barely moves under these reasonable alternatives, I feel safe; if not, I either collect more data or build a hierarchical prior that shares strength across groups. Jaynes made me see priors as explicit encoding of knowledge, not mysterious knobs to tune.
Chase
Chase
2025-09-07 12:11:39
My approach is a little nerdy and a touch formal, but Jaynes’ principles make it concise. I usually start with the desiderata he champions: consistency, invariance under reparameterization where appropriate, and logical coherence with known constraints. That leads to two practical techniques I use in tandem: maximum entropy for encoding soft constraints, and transformation-group arguments for symmetry-based invariance priors.

For example, if I'm modeling the position of an object where shifts in the origin don't matter, I treat the location parameter as having a uniform prior. For a scale parameter (like a standard deviation or a rate), I consider priors that are form-invariant under scaling — often leading to 1/σ-type behavior or Jeffreys’ priors as a starting point. Jaynes steered me away from blind defaults; instead I translate physical or logical symmetries into mathematical demands. I also watch out for improper priors that break normalization and perform posterior predictive checks: simulate data from the prior-predictive, see if simulated datasets look plausible given domain knowledge, and iterate. When I can, I embed vague beliefs into hierarchical models so the data can inform hyperparameters, blending Jaynes’ logic with modern robustness practices.
Knox
Knox
2025-09-07 18:41:38
I like to keep priors honest and minimalistic, and Jaynes’ voice helps me do that. He taught me to convert precise pieces of knowledge into constraints and then use maximum entropy to avoid sneaking in extra assumptions. If all I know is that a parameter is positive, I don’t force a detailed shape — I pick a distribution that reflects positivity and scale-invariance if that’s sensible.

I always complement the theoretical choice with simple checks: prior predictive sampling, sensitivity sweeps with alternative invariant priors, and sometimes a hierarchical layer if borrowing strength is natural. It’s a gentle workflow: encode knowledge, respect symmetries, test robustness, and be ready to collect more data if the prior still decides everything — which usually tells me I need to learn more rather than pretend certainty.
View All Answers
Scan code to download App

Related Books

Help Me
Help Me
Abigail Kinsington has lived a shelter life, stuck under the thumb of her domineering and abusive father. When his shady business dealings land him in trouble, some employees seeking retribution kidnap her as a punishment for her father. But while being held captive, she begins to fall for one of her captors, a misunderstood guy who found himself in over his head after going along with the crazy scheme of a co-worker. She falls head over heels for him. When she is rescued, she is sent back to her father and he is sent to jail. She thinks she has found a friend in a sympathetic police officer, who understands her. But when he tries turns on her, she wonders how real their connection is? Trapped in a dangerous love triangle between her kidnapper and her rescuer, Abby is more confused than she has ever been. Will she get out from under her father's tyrannical rule? Will she get to be with the man she loves? Does she even know which one that is? Danger, deception and dark obsession turn her dull life into a high stakes game of cat and mouse. Will she survive?
10
37 Chapters
Rejected, Princess Mate Selection Game
Rejected, Princess Mate Selection Game
"I reject you as my mate, you are your mother's accomplice to the sadism!" After my mother died, I was demoted to Omega by the Blackstone Pack, and my mate rejected me in public. I became an orphan Rogue. Unexpectedly, the alpha king found me and claimed me as his princess, and I have three half-brothers. The huge change in identity made the male Alphas of various packs focus on me, including my first mate, Alpha Caden. I wore a mask and listened to him coldly about his regrets. One of my brothers, Adrian, the heir of the alpha king, blocked me behind him, "You are my mate, don't look at any other male wolf." I was shocked, is my brother my second mate?
9.7
106 Chapters
Too Dead to Help
Too Dead to Help
My estranged husband suddenly barges into my parents' home, demanding to know where I am. He forces my mother to her knees and pushes my paralyzed father to the floor before beating him up. He even renders our four-year-old son half-dead. Why? Because his true love is disfigured and needs a skin graft to restore her looks. "Where is Victoria? She should be honored that she can do this for Amelia! Hand her over, or I'll kill all of you!" It's too bad I've been dead for a year.
11 Chapters
The Alpha Prince in his Mate Selection
The Alpha Prince in his Mate Selection
In the Kingdom of Raphbarg, there is a man named Alphonso, the crown prince of the Kingdom.The prince is loved by his country, his people, and his family.However--Of all the things that the Moon Goddess could give, a mate is even not on her list. There is no drug for his sick pheromones, only to choose for a Mate in Selection.Why did he have to choose a mate? What happened? "My Goddess, Lady Goddess on the moon, Who will be my mate of them all?" -Prince AlphonsoFind it out in this story :)
10
182 Chapters
Exchange Help with Mr. Wolf
Exchange Help with Mr. Wolf
Harriet Morrison is at her senior year at North Point High. She eats her lunch at the janitor’s closet and thought of meeting the legendary wolf who lives in the forest and will always be the talk of the small town she’s living in. She went home into her parents’ fight then at night, her mother’s death. Two weeks later, her father gets rid of her because she wasn’t her real daughter. She inherited a farmhouse from her late mother but entered the wrong house and found the legendary wolf with his gamma, Harriet heard him talking to the tomb of his long-lost lover, a girl in his past that he has fallen in love with. So, out of the heat of the moment she asked him if she could live with him, and in return, they could pretend they could be together in order for him to go to school and find his long-lost lover to which the wolf agreed and her bullies ran away, but each time they interviewed a girl from her school that looks a lot like his lover, they open up a new quest that got her to discover secrets on her own self, family, her past, and her true identity. Can Harriet handle all of it with the help of the legendary wolf? Or would she end up dead with all the misery and demise she got?
Not enough ratings
93 Chapters
Help! The CEO Is Seducing Me
Help! The CEO Is Seducing Me
“No matter how much you hate me, I will keep coming close to you. One day, you will be mine!” ..... What happens when a handsome rich CEO, is slapped by a waitress in front of his employees? His urge to possess the girl only increases and he will leave no stone unturned to come close to her. Ethan is an adamant man and now his eyes are set on the gorgeous girl, Hazel Hazel, a part time waitress, has a dream to become a successful interior designer. Unknowingly she ends up signing a contract with Ethan's company and is now stuck with him for two months in his home, on a secluded island. While Ethan wants to seduce her, Hazel only wants to concentrate on her job.
9.5
112 Chapters

Related Questions

How Does Et Jaynes Probability Theory Differ From Frequentist Theory?

4 Answers2025-09-03 10:46:46
I've been nerding out over Jaynes for years and his take feels like a breath of fresh air when frequentist methods get too ritualistic. Jaynes treats probability as an extension of logic — a way to quantify rational belief given the information you actually have — rather than merely long-run frequencies. He leans heavily on Cox's theorem to justify the algebra of probability and then uses the principle of maximum entropy to set priors in a principled way when you lack full information. That means you don't pick priors by gut or convenience; you encode symmetry and constraints, and let entropy give you the least-biased distribution consistent with those constraints. By contrast, the frequentist mindset defines probability as a limit of relative frequencies in repeated experiments, so parameters are fixed and data are random. Frequentist tools like p-values and confidence intervals are evaluated by their long-run behavior under hypothetical repetitions. Jaynes criticizes many standard procedures for violating the likelihood principle and being sensitive to stopping rules — things that, from his perspective, shouldn't change your inference about a parameter once you've seen the data. Practically that shows up in how you interpret intervals: a credible interval gives the probability the parameter lies in a range, while a confidence interval guarantees coverage across repetitions, which feels less directly informative to me. I like that Jaynes connects inference to decision-making and prediction: you get predictive distributions, can incorporate real prior knowledge, and often get more intuitive answers in small-data settings. If I had one tip, it's to try a maximum-entropy prior on a toy problem and compare posterior predictions to frequentist estimates — it usually opens your eyes.

What Are The Core Principles Of Et Jaynes Probability Theory?

4 Answers2025-09-03 09:20:06
If I had to boil Jaynes down to a handful of guiding lights, they'd be: probability as extended logic, maximum entropy as the least biased assignment given constraints, and symmetry/invariance for choosing priors. I love how Jaynes treats probabilities not as long-run frequencies but as degrees of plausibility — numbers that obey rational rules (think Cox's desiderata) so different lines of reasoning give consistent results. He pushes the maximum entropy principle hard: when all you know are some constraints (like averages), choose the distribution that maximizes Shannon entropy subject to those constraints. That way you don't smuggle in extra assumptions. He also insists priors should reflect symmetry and transformation groups — use the problem's invariances to pick noninformative priors rather than an ill-defined “ignorance.” Finally, and this is the practical kicker, update with Bayes' rule when you get data, and always be explicit about what information you're conditioning on. I keep a copy of 'Probability Theory: The Logic of Science' on my shelf and treat it like a toolkit: logic for setting up plausibilities, MaxEnt for turning constraints into distributions, and invariance arguments for fair priors.

Which Chapters Of Et Jaynes Probability Theory Are Most Essential?

4 Answers2025-09-03 18:37:24
Okay, dive in with me: if you only take a few chapters from 'Probability Theory: The Logic of Science', I’d grab the ones that build the whole way you think about uncertainty. Start with Jaynes’s foundational material — the chapters that explain probability as extended logic and derive the product and sum rules. Those are the philosophical and mathematical seeds that make the rest of the book click; without them, Bayes' theorem and conditionals feel like magic tricks instead of tools. After that, read the section on prior probabilities and transformation groups: Jaynes’s treatment of invariance and how to pick noninformative priors is pure gold, and it changes how you set up problems. Then move to the parts on the method of maximum entropy and on parameter estimation/approximation methods. Maximum entropy is the cleanest bridge between information theory and inference, and the estimation chapters show you how to actually compute credible intervals and compare models. If you like case studies, skim the applied chapters (spectral analysis, measurement errors) later; they show the ideas in action and are surprisingly practical. Personally, I flip between the core theory and the examples — theory to understand, examples to remember how to use it.

What Are Common Examples In Et Jaynes Probability Theory Exercises?

4 Answers2025-09-03 21:20:16
When I flip through problems inspired by Jaynes, the classics always pop up: biased coin estimation, urn problems, dice symmetry, and the ever-delicious applications of maximum entropy. A typical exercise will have you infer the bias of a coin after N tosses using a Beta prior, or derive the posterior predictive for the next toss — that little sequence of Beta-Binomial calculations is like comfort food. Jaynes also loves urn problems and variations on Bertrand's paradox, where you wrestle with what the principle of indifference really means and how choices of parameterization change probabilities. He then stretches those ideas into physics and information theory: deriving the Gaussian, exponential, and Poisson distributions from maximum-entropy constraints, or getting the canonical ensemble by maximizing entropy with an energy constraint. I've used those exercises to explain how statistical mechanics and Bayesian inference are cousins, and to show friends why the 'right' prior sometimes comes from symmetry or from maximum entropy. Throw in Monty Hall style puzzles, Laplace’s rule of succession, and simple sensor-noise inference examples and you’ve covered most of the recurring motifs — problems that are conceptually elegant but also great for coding quick Monte Carlo checks.

Who Are The Best Modern Texts After Et Jaynes Probability Theory?

4 Answers2025-09-03 14:53:20
If Jaynes' 'Probability Theory: The Logic of Science' lit a fire for you, I found the natural next steps split into three flavors: conceptual, applied, and rigorous math. On the conceptual/Bayesian side I keep going back to 'Bayesian Data Analysis' by Gelman et al. — it’s expansive, honest about practical pitfalls, and full of real examples. For a warm, conversational bridge between intuition and practice, 'Statistical Rethinking' by Richard McElreath rewired the way I build models: his code-first, example-driven approach makes Bayesian ideas stick. If you want a very hands-on, tutorial-style companion, John Kruschke’s 'Doing Bayesian Data Analysis' is delightful. For computational and machine-learning perspectives, Kevin P. Murphy’s 'Machine Learning: a Probabilistic Perspective' and Bishop’s 'Pattern Recognition and Machine Learning' show how probabilistic thinking powers algorithms. For foundational probability with measure-theoretic rigor, 'Foundations of Modern Probability' by Olav Kallenberg is brutal but rewarding, and Rick Durrett’s 'Probability: Theory and Examples' balances clarity with depth. I usually alternate between these books depending on whether I need intuition, code, or proofs.

Where Can I Download Et Jaynes Probability Theory PDF Legally?

4 Answers2025-09-03 22:58:22
Okay, quick and friendly: if you want a legal download of E. T. Jaynes' famous book, look first at the publisher. Cambridge University Press sells electronic versions of 'Probability Theory: The Logic of Science' — that's the most straightforward, aboveboard way to get a PDF or an ebook copy. If you have access through a university, your library might already subscribe to Cambridge e-books, so you could read or download it via your institution. Another legit route is major ebook vendors: Google Play Books and Amazon (Kindle) often carry the title. Those aren’t always PDFs, but they’re licensed ebooks you can buy immediately. If buying isn’t an option, try your local or university library: WorldCat can show nearby physical copies and many libraries participate in interlibrary loan if they don’t own it. Finally, check Open Library/Internet Archive for a borrowable digital copy — they lend legally under controlled digital lending. If you’re unsure whether a PDF you find online is legal, follow the publisher’s page or contact them directly; I’ve done that once and they were helpful. Happy reading — it’s a dense, brilliant book, so get a comfy chair and good coffee.

Why Do Statisticians Still Cite Et Jaynes Probability Theory Today?

4 Answers2025-09-03 03:08:14
What keeps Jaynes on reading lists and citation trails decades after his papers? For me it's the mix of clear philosophy, practical tools, and a kind of intellectual stubbornness that refuses to accept sloppy thinking. When I first dug into 'Probability Theory: The Logic of Science' I was struck by how Jaynes treats probability as extended logic — not merely frequencies or mystical priors, but a coherent calculus for reasoning under uncertainty. That reframing still matters: it gives people permission to use probability where they actually need to make decisions. Beyond philosophy, his use of Cox's axioms and the maximum entropy principle gives concrete methods. Maximum entropy is a wonderfully pragmatic rule: encode what you know, and otherwise stay maximally noncommittal. I find that translates directly to model-building, whether I'm sketching a Bayesian prior or cleaning up an ill-posed inference. Jaynes also connects probability to information theory and statistical mechanics in ways that appeal to both physicists and data people, so his work lives at multiple crossroads. Finally, Jaynes writes like he’s hashing things out with a friend — opinionated, rigorous, and sometimes cranky — which makes the material feel alive. People still cite him because his perspective helps them ask better questions and build cleaner, more honest models. For me, that’s why his voice keeps showing up in citation lists and lunchtime debates.

Can Et Jaynes Probability Theory Explain Bayesian Model Selection?

4 Answers2025-09-03 06:03:41
Totally — Jaynes gives you the conceptual scaffolding to understand Bayesian model selection, and I get excited every time I think about it because it ties logic, information, and probability together so cleanly. In Jaynes' world probability is extended logic: you assign plausibilities to hypotheses and update them with data using Bayes' theorem. For model selection that means comparing posterior probabilities of different models, which collapses to comparing their marginal likelihoods (a.k.a. evidence) when the prior model probabilities are equal. Jaynes' maximum-entropy arguments also give guidance on constructing priors when you want them to encode only the information you actually have — that’s crucial because the marginal likelihood integrates the likelihood across the prior, and the choice of prior can make or break model comparisons. That said, Jaynes doesn’t hand you a turnkey computational recipe. The philosophical and information-theoretic explanation is beautiful and powerful, but in practice you still wrestle with marginal likelihood estimation, sensitivity to priors, and paradoxes like Lindley’s. I often pair Jaynes’ book 'Probability Theory: The Logic of Science' with modern computational tools (nested sampling, bridge sampling) and predictive checks so the theory and practice reinforce each other.
Explore and read good novels for free
Free access to a vast number of good novels on GoodNovel app. Download the books you like and read anywhere & anytime.
Read books for free on the app
SCAN CODE TO READ ON APP
DMCA.com Protection Status